Revised as of
15 Mar 2023
In simple terms, pragmatics studies how meaning is communicated by a speaker and interpreted by a listener, in actual situations.
Yep, it’s “communication”, because a conversation can be verbal, written, action, or symbols.
One of the keys is that the meanings of words and phrases, in everyday language, are constantly implied and not explicitly stated. It also depends on the listener understanding the context.
Part of that implication is the difference between “what is said” and “what is meant”. To make it even more complex, the same word can have different meanings in different settings.
Hey, can you please pass the salt?
I like that comment Professor Jenny Thomas (Thomas) makes about pragmatics being a negotiation of meaning between speaker and listener. The context and meaning of an utterance.
That salt? The literal interpretation asks if you can physically perform this task. The pragmatic, implied, meaning is that you pass the salt to the person requesting it.
NOTE: The primary linguists on Pragmatics are H.P. Grice, John R. Searle, William C. Mann, and John L. Austin. Just so’s you know, they agree and disagree, use similar or different terms, and put subcategories everywhere.
“When a diplomat says yes, he means perhaps;
“When he says perhaps, he means no;
“When he says no, he is not a diplomat.”
– Voltaire, Escandell, 1993.
Just to warn you, I’m not a linguist. I’m an editor, and this part of theoretical linguistics has got to be the most disorganized load of “knowledge” I’ve ever come across. And that’s the last of the simple terms . . .
Other Posts on Theoretical Linguistics
Other posts on the primary theoretical categories can be explored:
- Intro to Theoretical Linguistics
- Generative – the theory that human language speakers have an idea of what the rules are and are able to learn in a short time with little effort
- Phonetics – the study of the physical production, acoustics, and hearing of speech sounds
- Phonology – the abstract study of the sound systems of languages in their cognitive aspects
- Semantics – the study of words and meanings
- Syntax – the study of how words and phrases make sentences
Linguistics is . . .
. . . the systematic study of the nature, structure, and variation of language (of which grammar is a part), which describes how people use language. For the writer, how words are used (or spelled!) determines a character’s social and educational level and the time period for the story.
As I discover more examples, also-known-ases, and additions, I’ll update this post. If you have a suggestion, I would appreciate you contacting me. If you found this post on “Theoretical Pragmatics” interesting, consider subscribing to KD Did It, if you’d like to track this post for future updates.
Pragmatics | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Part of Speech: Linguistics, Theoretical | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Definition: The study of how people understand the relationships between words, people engaged in the conversation, and the context of words by interpreting the meaning based on the manner, place, time, etc., of an utterance, including:
Speech Act TheoryConversational ImplicatureRhetorical Structure Theory (RST)Reference Management
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Near-side vs Far-side Pragmatics | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Near-side | Far-side | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
|
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: Needs the facts about the: | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Meshes semantics and pragmatics |
Credit to: Sindhu |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Speech Act Theory | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Definition: Acts of communication using language or motion → when words are actions: ordering, apologizing, sentencing, marrying, running, promising, writing, etc.
A.k.a. communicative act Credit to: Pragmatics |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
A Speech Act includes . . . | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Asking for a glass of water.
Promising to drink a glass of water. Threatening to drink a glass of water. Ordering someone to drink a glass of water, etc. Ask for a glass of water by pointing to a pitcher and miming the act of drinking. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Distinguishing Among Speech Acts | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: The context or the setting will determine the force of a speech act, as well as using their judgement and background knowledge of the language and the culture.
Credit to: Schiffman |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
The Queen of Hearts: “Off with their heads!”
If someone else says it in another setting, it has a different force. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Two Ways of Performing Speech Acts: | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Direct Speech Act | Indirect Speech Act | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Definition: Bluntly reports the exact words that were said or written.
Direct speech also uses performative verbs in the three types. A.k.a. oratio recta, reported direct |
Definition: Communicates in a roundabout manner, expecting the listener to understand the obliquely stated context.
A.k.a. implicit speech act, oratio obliqua, reported indirect speech |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
There are three types of direct and indirect speech types: | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Assertion | Definition: Uses a declarative sentence committing the speaker to convey information that is true or false.
They refer to statements, descriptions, classifications, explanations, and clarifications. A.k.a. assertive |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Order and Request | Definition: Uses an imperative sentence type to cause others to behave in certain ways. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Question | Definition: An interrogative sentence type that elicits information. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Locutionary Speech Act | Definition: The basic act of utterance, of producing a meaningful linguistic expression, a.k.a. sentence, usually has a purpose: | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
When performing a locutionary act, you are:
There are three types of force typically cited in Speech Act Theory: |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Is there any salt?
Asks a question about the salt. John claims that Mary is happy. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Utterance Act | Definition: What is actually said by a speaker in words and sentences. And not necessarily meaning to try to affect anyone else. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The utterance doesn’t have to make sense. It could be a sentence in a foreign language you are uttering to practice pronunciation.
An utterance can also be writing or signals. Alston calls the nonlinguistic devices that one can use in these types of acts sentence surrogates. A.k.a. sentential act |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Did the paper arrive?
We’re heading out to church. Je suis ravi de vous rencontrer. Hope you have a good time. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Propositional Act | Definition: However the sentence is constructed, as long as the same content is in it, it’s propositional. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Will John leave the room?
John will leave the room. John, leave the room! Would that John left the room. If John will leave the room, I’ll leave also.” |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Illocutionary Speech Act | Definition: An utterance act saying something and doing something at the same time by way of conventions, using sentences that are all affirmative, declarative, and in the present tense and issuing a message. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
A literal illocutionary speech act is when the statement is the actual meaning.
A non-literal illocutionary speech act is when the statement does not mean what it says but something else instead. In these types of sentences, the speaker is the subject who, by uttering the sentence, is accomplishing some additional action, such as daring, resigning, nominating, etc.
A.k.a. illocutionary force Credit to: Searle, 47. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
It’s gonna rain.
Makes the person hearing this prepare and/or wonder if it will really rain. A judge sentences someone. Incitement at a protest rally that results in rioting. Is there any salt? A request for salt. The black cat is stupid. He urged me to shoot her. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rhetic Act | Definition: Characterized, roughly, as the act of uttering the words in a sentence with a specific meaning and reference.
Performance of an act using those phatic words with a certain more-or-less definite sense and reference. Credit to: Austin |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Deixis | Definition: A reference to a person, object, event, an action in time, social relationships, locate parts of a text in relation to other parts, which relies on the situational context. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Five major types of diectic markers:
Two kinds of social deixis:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Sorry I missed you.
I’m in my other office. Back in an hour. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: A reference can include first and second person pronouns. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: A reference can include demonstrative articles. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: A reference can include expressions of time and place, AND we need to know when or where the utterance was said. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
“I’m over here!”
You would need to know who “I” referred to, as well as where “here” is. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Phatic Act | Definition: Uttering of certain words, belonging to and as belonging to, a certain vocabulary, conforming to a certain grammar.
To perform a phatic, a phonetic act must be performed. A.k.a. phatic expression, small talk |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
William: “Morning, Paul.” Paul: “Oh, morning, William, how are you?” William: “Fine, thanks. Have a good weekend.” Paul: “Yes, thanks. Catch you later.” William: “OK, see you.” |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
There’s a spider on your lap. This is the performance of a phonic act. Saying it and recognizing that it is English is a phatic act. Credit to: Davis |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Phonic Act | Definition: The physical act of producing a certain sequence of vocal sounds (spoken language), or a set of written symbols (written language).
It’s also a methodology to teach reading and writing skills and/or teaching elementary reading based on the phonetic interpretation of normal spelling. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
fpioqwu wiou sadly Jill have blue are row, row, row your boat |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Communicative Illocutionary Act | Definition: The speaker intends the hearer to recognize the point of their utterance through content, context, AND for the point to be recognized. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Its fulfillment consists in its recognition, i.e., communicative intention:
Credit to: Bach, chapt 3 |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Acknowledgment Speech Act | Definition: Expresses their attitudes about objects and facts of the world toward the hearer or the intention that the utterance will meet some social expectations regarding the expression of feelings.
A.k.a. expressive |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
When the speaker is given a slice of cheese and likes it, then they will say “I like it” or “thank you”, etc. Shows how the speaker feels about a situation. I praise you for receiving the Pulitzer Prize. I curse the day you were born. I compliment you on your excellent choice of wine. I honor you for winning a gold metal in the Olympics. Credit to: Written |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Commissive Speech Act | Definition: Expresses the speaker’s intention to do something in the future and the belief that her utterance obliges her to do it. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
I will come to your home tonight. An utterance in which the speaker commits that they will come to the speaker’s home at night. Karen will offer to give you a ride to the airport, if you need it. I pledge to donate $500 to your favorite charity. Credit to: Written |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Constative Speech Act | Definition: Words that describe a situation and is true or false. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
John denies that ever happened. Are you disagreeing with me?! I confirmed my flight a couple hours ago. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Declarative Speech Act | Definition: Brings about the state of affairs to which the speaker refers.
A.k.a. declaration |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
I pass. Said while playing bridge. I bless the two of you. Said by a priest during the marriage ceremony. I abbreviate the Committee for Untested Trials and Experiments as CUTE. I name this dog Butchie. Credit to: Written |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Directive Speech Act | Definition: Aims to make someone else do something that the speaker desires. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Could you lend me a pen? Lend me a pen! The speaker requests a pen from someone else, they indirectly order the other person to lend him a pen. I beg you not to go out during this hurricane. I request that you be here tomorrow one-half hour earlier. I permit you to camp out on my front lawn. I recommend that you eat fewer foods with cholesterol. I implore you to leave that no-good husband of yours. I require my students to do homework assignments. If said directly to students. Credit to: Written |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Representative Speech Act | Definition: Commits a speaker to the truth of the expressed proposition.
A.k.a. assertive |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
I’m a good guy. Shows that the speaker wants the hearer believe that the speaker is a good guy. I hereby testify that I sold that property on July 3, l989. I predict that there will be a stock market crash later this year. I acknowledge that I promised to take you to Las Vegas. I require my students to do homework assignments. If reported to someone else. Credit to: Written |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Conventional Illocutionary Act | Definition: Acts performed with certain communicative intentions whose recognition by the hearer is necessary for the acts to be successful. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Success is a matter of convention, not intention; no communicative intention needs to be involved.
There are two classes (five per Austin*): Credit to: Bach, chapter 6 |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Behabitive | Definition: Expresses attitudes or social behavior towards someone. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
I apologize for what I said. Dean is in there praising her to the skies. He’s challenging her for the leadership. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Commissive | Definition: Commits yourself to doing something. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The mayor vowed that he would follow through on that project. I’ll pledge $300. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Effective | Definition: When produced by the appropriate person in appropriate circumstances produces a change, a new fact in an institutional context. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The President of the United States states that he vetoes a piece of legislation. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Exercitive | Definition: Exercises powers, rights, or influence. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The boss just appointed you to the board. Are you voting this election? |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Expositive | Definition: Acts that clarify reasons, arguments, or communications and makes plain how we are using words | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Every day, Elaine affirmed her self-worth. No, I’m simply asking you. She’s in there describing the perpetrator. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Verdictive | Definition: Does not produce facts, but determines/judges facts, natural or institutional, with an official, binding effect in the institutional context. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The jury brought in a verdict of guilt. It does not create the fact of guilt, but settles the issue of guilt in a binding way. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Perlocutionary | Definition: Utterances that have an effect on the listener, initiating a set of consequences such as affecting the listener’s thoughts, emotions, or even their physical actions, which can be unintentional. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Credit to: Butler |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Hate speech acts upon its listener.
Is there any salt? Causes someone to pass the salt. Maybe. Please find the black cat. He persuaded me to shoot her. He convinced me not to shoot her. I’ve just made some cookies. The listener may interpret this utterance as a request that they react by appreciating the smell or as an offer to try one. I’m hungry. The listener could be persuaded to make a sandwich for the speaker. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Constative Speech Act | Definition: Depends on the facts and can only be judged in reference to them. It can be true or false. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Successful constative utterance:
Problem constative utterance:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Performative Verbs | Definition: Explicit verbs that incite, inspire, or denote action carried out by speakers. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Acts upon the world by doing something, not saying something. It is not necessarily true or false.
They are used in first person singular, simple present, indicative, or active. It can be: |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Examples include: | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
“I do take this woman to be my lawful wedded wife.” Uttered in the course of the marriage ceremony. “I name this ship the Queen Elizabeth.” Uttered when smashing the bottle against the stern. “I give and bequeath my watch to my brother.” As occurring in a will. “I bet you sixpence it will rain tomorrow.” |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Successful Performative | Rule: To be successful, a performative utterance must:
A.k.a. felicitous performative, felicity condition, happy |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Essential Condition | Definition: The speaker says what they say, and both speaker and hearer take the utterance to be performative. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
“I promise to do my homework.”
Both of you think this is a promise. If you quote yourself to a friend as saying “I told my teacher ‘I promise to do my homework’,” the quote — though identical in its locutionary properties — fails to promise because it has become part of a representative act reporting on the promise. The involved parties intend to create a marriage bond. Person pronouncing the words must believe what they are saying. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Preparatory Condition | Definition: The speaker can do (doesn’t mean they are able to do but that they are allowed to do) what they say, that both speaker and hearer agree that it is situationally appropriate for them to perform the speech act. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
“I promise to do my homework.”
You are actually a student in the teacher’s class and the homework has been assigned. If these conditions were not met, you’d have no homework and thus, no need to promise to do it. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Sincerity Condition | Definition: The speaker means what they say, that both speaker and hearer take the utterance to be intentional, to accurately represent the wish of the speaker and the hearer’s understanding that the utterance expresses that wish. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The common expression “in good faith” illustrates the basic premise of the sincerity condition.
“I promise to do my homework.” Both of you think that statement is a promise, a verbal contract suggesting that you want to do the homework and possess the requisite capacities to complete it. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Failed Performative | Definition: States an action, but no one acts, reacts, or has no effect.
A.k.a. infelicitous, unhappy |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: A performative may be successful in one context, and a failure in another. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
If two gay men marry, their friends and family may recognize their vows as a happy and binding promise, but the state may not. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: Saying something can also be viewed from three different perspectives: | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Entail | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Definition: The relationship between two sentences where the truth of one requires the truth of the other. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
The president was assassinated.
The president is dead. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Implication | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Definition: Stating a constative implies that you believe it. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
The cat is on the mat.
Implies I believe that’s where the cat is. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Presupposition | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Definition: An implicit assumption about the world or background belief relating to an utterance whose truth is taken for granted in discourse. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Hetty’s children are bald.
Presupposes that Hetty has children. Jane no longer writes fiction. Presupposes that Jane once wrote fiction. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: Use the hereby test to determine if a sentence is a performative utterance is whether or not you can insert hereby before the verb. If the resulting sentence doesn’t make sense, it is not a performative. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
I hereby name this ship Sojourner
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Conversational Implicature | Includes: | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Explicature | Definition: Explicit communicated assumption that says everything we want to communicate and is often supplemented with contextual information. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
No one goes there anymore.
Hardly anyone of any worth/taste goes to that location, any more. There’s milk in the fridge. There’s milk of sufficient quantity/quality for adding to coffee in the fridge. Max: “Would you like to stay for supper?” Amy: “No thanks, I’ve already eaten.” Amy has already eaten supper this evening. Alan: “Do you want to join us for supper?” 1. Lisa: “No, thanks. I’ve eaten.” 2. Lisa: “No, thanks. I’ve already eaten supper.” 3. Lisa: “No, thanks. I’ve already eaten tonight.” 4. Lisa: “No, thanks. I’ve already eaten supper tonight.” All four answers communicate the same overall meaning but also the same explicatures and implicatures. The second answer is the least explicit while the last answer is the most explicit. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Implicature | Definition: An indirect illocutionary speech act with something the speaker suggests or implies with an utterance, even though it is not literally expressed and is characteristically far richer than what they directly express. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Implicatures can aid in communicating more efficiently than by explicitly saying everything we want to communicate.
It is a form of literary device which uses a word or phrase that departs from its literal meaning, such as irony, metaphors and intended meanings, in order to achieve a special effect or meaning, speech, or writing. There are two types:
A.k.a. conversational implicature (yep, that’s besides the primary category) Credit to: Implicature; Horn; Semantics |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Dr. Gregory House: “How many friends do you have?”
Lucas Douglas: “Seventeen.” Dr. Gregory House: “Seriously? Do you keep a list or something?” Lucas Douglas: “No, I knew this conversation was really about you, so I gave you an answer so you could get back to your train of thought.” – Hugh Laurie and Michael Weston. “Not Cancer.” House, M.D. 2008. Husband: “How much longer will you be?” Wife: “Mix yourself a drink.” The assumption is that the husband and wife are going out, and the wife’s reply implies that it’ll be awhile. Jim Halpert: “I don’t think I’ll be here in 10 years.” Michael Scott: “That’s what I said. That’s what she said.” Jim Halpert: “That’s what who said?” Michael Scott: “I never know, I just say it. I say stuff like that, you know – to lighten the tension when things sort of get hard.” Jim Halpert: “That’s what she said.” – John Krasinski and Steve Carell. “Survivor Man.” The Office. 2007. Alan: “Are you going to Paul’s party?” Barb: “I have to work.” The implication is that Barb is not going to Paul’s party. Carla: “How’s the weather over there?” Don: “The weather’s lovely.” Don is using irony (he’s a truck driver trying to get over the continental divide during a blizzard), as the weather is terrible while Carla is a dispatcher in Denver, where it is sunny and dry. You’re late to work, and your boss says, “What time do you call this ?!” in an angry voice. By examining the context and your boss’s tone of voice, you can infer that your boss does not want to know the time but actually wants to know why you are late. I could eat a horse. In reading the context, we know that he doesn’t intend to eat a horse, but that he is very hungry. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Conventional Implicature | Definition: Blurs the distinction between what is said and what is implied. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
A conventional implicature is:
Credit to: Potts |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
He was poor but honest.
Implies an unspecified contrast between poverty and honesty. When speaking of another man, he says “he hasn’t been to prison yet”. Up to the point of speaking, “he” hasn’t been to prison, yet. It does imply that he is the sort of person likely to yield to the temptation provided by his occupation, based on common knowledge. Even KEN knows it’s unethical. Ken is the least likely to know that it’s unethical. John is hungry but he won’t stay for supper. We might expect that if John is hungry, he will stay for supper. Manfred Krifka was in Moscow last spring too. Some other given person than Manfred was in Moscow last spring. Masha managed to start the car. It required some effort to start the car, and Masha really did make an effort to start the car. Bush failed to read the report. Bush had an opportunity and tried, or should have tried, to read it. Alfred has still not come. Alfred was expected to have come by now. Credit to: Partee |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Cooperative Principle | Definition: The unspoken agreement of cooperation between participants in a conversation in interpreting the speaker’s meaning, a.k.a. conversational implicature, in a series of speech acts, including greetings, inquiries, congratulations, comments, invitations, requests, accusations, etc. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
There are four maxims to the Cooperative Principle:
Politeness and all of the other speech act formulae vary from culture to culture:
Conversational implicatures have the following characteristics: A.k.a. nonconventional implicature Credit to: Pragmatics |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
John has three sons.
Conversationally implies that John has no more than three sons. I ask you to lunch and you reply, “I have a one o’clock class I’m not prepared for.” You have implied that you will not be coming to lunch, although you haven’t literally said so, because you need to prepare for your class. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Manner Maxim | Definition: Contributions should be clearly understood, avoiding obscurity and ambiguity — in particular, they should be orderly and brief. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
You talk with a neighbor about his new car. He has trouble staying on topic and starts talking about his favorite TV show. He doesn’t look at you when you talk and doesn’t laugh at your jokes. He keeps talking, even when you look at your watch and say, ‘Wow. It’s getting late.’ You finally leave, thinking about how hard it is to talk with him.”
In this scenario, the speaker is just talking about a new car and his favorite TV show. But the listener interprets the signs the speaker is using — not looking at the listener and not laughing at his jokes — as the speaker being unaware of the listener’s views (let alone his presence) and monopolizing his time. Credit to: Nordquist |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Quality Maxim | Definition: Speakers’ contributions ought to be truthful and provide evidence for statements. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
He: “Looks like it might rain!”
She: “Oh, yes, there’s going to be ten inches of rain, followed by snow, at least 20 inches, then hail; then a plague of locusts; and, the sun will shine from midnight until 2 a.m. Then there will be silence in heaven for about half an hour, and when the seventh seal is opened . . .” He: “Where do you get your information?” |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Quantity Maxim | Definition: Speakers’ contributions should be as informative as required without overdoing it. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Parent: Did you finish your homework?
Child: I finished my algebra. Parent: Well, get busy and finish your English, too! The child’s answer implicates that the unmentioned subjects are not done. Mary: “Hi, John, how are ya?” John: “Oh, not so good, Mary. I just had a tooth out, then last week I had an epidural injection in my spine, followed by restorative surgery on my little toe; you should have seen it, it was horrible, and you wouldn’t believe what the surgeon charged, I just got the bill! Our health care system is outrageous, and the traffic on the way to work today! Unbelievable!” Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Relevance Maxim | Definition: Contributions should relate to the purposes of the exchange without adding superfluous or irrelevant material.
Organize your utterances so that they are relevant at the time of the utterance. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Ford: “You should prepare yourself for the jump into hyperspace; it’s unpleasantly like being drunk.”
Arthur: “What’s so unpleasant about being drunk?” Ford: “Just ask a glass of water.” – Douglas Adams, The Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy. Credit to: Ladusaw |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Cancelable Implicature | Definition: When the second sentence cancels out what the first sentence states. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
John passed some of his exams. In fact, he passed all of them.
The first sentence says he passed “some” of them when, in truth, he passed them all. The second, truthful, sentence cancels out the first. A: How many exams did John pass? B: Some. In fact, he passed all of them. Again, the answer’s first sentence is not truthful, which makes it cancelable. Some of the students came to the party. In fact, I believe all of them came. Some? When the second sentence says they all came? Nope, cancels out again. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Non-detachable Implicature | Definition: It’s not possible to find another way of saying the same thing. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
A: “Are you going to the party tonight?” B1: “I don’t like parties.” B2: “I’m not into parties.” Both of B’s statements imply that B won’t go to the party. War is war. Five bucks is five bucks. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Calculable Implicature | Definition: Capable of being worked out. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
All but one of the papers at the Reading Party were good. Three of the papers at the Reading Party were good. The papers by the German students at the Reading Party were good. Half of the papers at the Reading Party were good. One, three, the papers, and half each provide a calculation of the quality of the papers. He is an Englishman, therefore he is brave. He is an Englishman, and he is brave. Therefore makes this a calculation. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Scalar Implicature | Definition: Attributes an implicit meaning beyond the explicit or literal meaning of an utterance, and which suggests that the utterer had a reason for not using a more informative or stronger term on the same scale.
A.k.a. quality implicature |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Bill: “I have some of my money in cash.” Suggests to a hearer that Bill does not have all his money in cash. Some students can afford a new car. Tells us that not all students can afford a new car. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Violations of the Cooperative Principles | Rule: Indirect speech acts and shared knowledge that are mixed up or failure to observe them makes for uncooperative speech acts, confusion, and other problems.
Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
A: “Did Pamela pay you back the money?”
B: “Is the Pope Catholic?” A: “She’s honest as the day is long!” |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Politeness Conventions | Definition: Conventionalized ways of communicating that a culture sees as polite and appropriate.
This differs from culture to culture and subculture to subculture. It may involve various kinds of illocutionary acts, titles and address forms, special honorific suffixes, the passive voice, circumlocutions, or any other kinds of locutions. Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Positive Politeness | Definition: Making utterances that are:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Sure, I can do that.
I hope you have a happy birthday. Please, after you. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Negative Politeness | Definition: Avoiding saying things that are:
No words are used, but politeness is maintained, although there are exceptions. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
A: “I’m a vegetarian, and I don’t believe in killing any animals for any purpose!” B looks at her feet to see if she’s wearing shoes made of leather. In 1546, Catherine Parr, the sixth and final wife of Henry VIII, deflected the king’s anger by presenting her disagreements as opinions in order to distract Henry from his health issues. Credit to: Nordquist Keep quiet! Shut up! is even ruder. The polite version: “Would you mind keeping quiet?” Credit to: Nordquist Would you mind if I stepped ahead of you? I only have two things to purchase. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Structure of Conversation | Definition: There is a covert structure of conversations, involving a number of different elements:
Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Adjacency Pairs | Definition: Certain kinds of turn-taking have specific follow-ups:
Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
A: “Sorry about last night!”
B: “No problem; we were all pretty tired.” But not: B: “Where’d you get those shoes?” |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Conversational Routine | Definition: Uses fixed expressions, a.k.a. routines, that often have specific functions in conversation and give conversational discourse the quality of naturalness. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Routines include:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
This one’s on me.
I don’t believe a word of it. I don’t get the point. You look great today. As I was saying, . . . Nearly time. Got everything? I’ll be making a move then. I see what you mean. Let me think about it. Just looking, thanks. I’ll be with you in a minute. It doesn’t matter. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Opening Sequence | Definition: People ordinarily begin in conventional ways: greetings, general questions or comments about the weather, sports, etc.
Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Closing Sequence | Definition: People conventionally prepare to end a conversation by summing up, using other locutions followed by several repetitions of farewells.
Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Politeness | Definition: Respectful communication structure that will differ from culture to culture and involving the maxims of the Cooperative Principle. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
It may involve various kinds of illocutionary acts, titles and address forms, special honorific suffixes, the passive voice circumlocutions, or any other kinds of locutions.
Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: One or more maxims may be ignored with the intention of lightening bad news. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Ignoring the quantity maxim by being more verbose than usual in order to convey sympathy. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: The structure can change depending on the speaker’s relationship to the listener — family, close friend, business acquaintance, stranger, etc. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
How ya doin’?
I hope you are enjoying good health. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: Situations vary, requiring different responses. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Credit to: Politeness Theory |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Repairs | Definition: When people don’t say what they intended to, need to edit a previous statement, misspeak themselves, or say something backwards, they then need to fix the utterance, i.e., they make repairs.
A.k.a. self-repair Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
I am going to Paris on Tuesday.
I mean, on Thursday. In fact, on Thursday. I mean introduces a repair. In fact introduces either a repair or a cancellation. A: “Who has two children?” B: “Maria. I mean, she has three.” I mean introduces a repair. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Turn-taking and Pausing | Definition: People usually don’t all talk at once; they signal that they are done by using certain phrases.
Credit to: Schiffman |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rhetorical Structure Theory (RST) | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Definition: Organizes text and characterizes its structure — the presence or absence of coherence — in terms of the relations that hold between parts of text using a hierarchy of phrases/sentences.
RST only describes the processes of creating or reading and understanding text with an emphasis on social context. Judgement is required in determining RST. RST basics include:
Key elements include: The original reason for studying RST was developing a theory of text structure in computer programs, serving as an analytical tool, and as a tool for text generation. Credit to: Mann |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Text Span | Definition: Generally a clause that consists of a:
If a text span is defined in functional terms instead of orthographic terms, it can be interrupted when normally a text span is NOT interrupted by another text span. A.k.a. span |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Nucleus-satellite Relations | Definition: Most common of structural patterning with one member of a pair of text spans more central (nucleus) and one more peripheral (the satellite). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Other nucleus text parts will have structural similarities with other nuclei.
* Satellite may come before the nucleus A.k.a. asymmetry of relations |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Types of nucleus-satellite relations include: | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Circumstance Relation | Definition: The nucleus expresses the event(s) or idea(s) occurring in the interpretive context while the satellite is an interpretive context of situation or time. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Cleaning agents on the burnished surface of the Ectype coating actually remove build-up from the head, 2, while lubricating it at the same time.
“Cleaning agents … actually remove build-up” is the locus of effect of the nucleus and the circumstance relation while “while lubricating it at the same time”, the satellite, provides a framework within which to interpret the nucleus. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Evidence Relation | Definition: Relates two text spans, one of which (the satellite) provides evidence for the claim put forth in the nucleus. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The program as published for calendar year 1980 really works.
“The program . . . really works” is the locus of effect of the nucleus and the evidence relation while “as published . . . year 1980” is the satellite. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Size | Definition: RST works for all sizes, from clauses to groups of paragraphs, requiring: | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Organization | Definition: Functionally significant texts — elements of patterns in which texts are combined to create larger texts and whole texts. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Unity and Coherence | Definition: Incorporates every part into a single connected analysis. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Unity and Coherence Arise from Imputed Function | Definition: A chunk of text that contributes to the single purpose of the writer to achieve a single effect.
This is achieved through: |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Relations | Definition: The most frequent structural pattern, it identifies particular relationships that can hold between two non-overlapping text spans — that are part of “speaker meaning”, the way that people use language to inform or entertain or persuade.
Multiple relations can occur in any text. There are two fields in a relations definition: A.k.a. coherence relations |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Constraints | Definition: A field in which a set of constraints exist on: | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Effect | Definition: The reader judges whether it is plausible that the writer wants the specified condition(s).
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Relational Composition | Definition: Strongly dominant relational patterns link parts together to form larger parts.
Other assumptions include:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Nature of Relations | Definition: Text structuring relations are functional, reflecting:
There is no single function, but a combination of:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Number of Relations | Definition: It’s most common that the set of relations used in a text is pulled from a small set of highly recurrent relations common to a culture.
It does allow for additional previously unused relations. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Schema | Definition: Based on the relations, a schema defines patterns that allows a text span to be analyzed in terms of other spans.
For each relation, there is a corresponding schema. Constraints that apply to a structural analysis of a text include:
Credit to: Mann |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Schema Application | Definition: Defines the ways a schema can be represented by an actual example.
The structure of an entire text is defined in terms of composition of schema applications. Three conventions determine possible applications of a schema:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Three Kinds of Structure | Definition: A theory of text organization that describes relations that hold between parts of text.
Three kinds of structure, e.g., building blocks, that can mix and match with abandon: Structures that follow a: Credit to: Pragmatics |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Holistic Structure | Definition: Incompressible, it applies to the complete system of language — how the parts of a whole relate to each other to form the whole. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The body of a letter uses what our culture expects:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Relational Structure | Definition: Conversational influence attempts that are often organized around requests, hints, and prompts.
A.k.a. relational discourse structure |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Syntactic Structure | Definition: A fancy way to say “the arrangement of words, phrases, and clauses in a sentence” that provides the sentence with meaning.
The foundation of a sentence is the subject-predicate. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The senators objected to the plans proposed by the generals.
The senators proposed the plans objected to by the generals. Using the same words but rearranged, these sentences say exactly the opposite of each other. He read the book new. We fed some dogs hungry. I saw the house white. The grammatical mistakes of these sentences indicate that adjectives cannot follow a noun. He read the new book. We fed some hungry dogs. I painted the house white. Ahh, yes, it makes more sense that the adjective comes before the noun. Credit to: Nordquist |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Hierarchy | Definition: The outline approach with text organized by primary ideas and drilling down to the specifics — similar to an outline for a research paper with its main points which lead to subheadings with information that supports your thesis statement.
Consider how articles are structured for newsletters, magazines, newspapers, and blogs. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Homogeneity of Hierarchy | Definition: A set of patterns, a.k.a. RST schemas, using one set of structural patterns from the largest (letter body, magazine article body, etc.) down to a two-clause combination.
There is likely to be rank-scale or size-scale of sections and paragraphs with their own distinct functional descriptions and principles of relational composition. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Reference Management | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Definition: The speaker considers what the listener knows and lays out the sentence so the listener will understand it.
Management splits into: Credit to: Pragmatics |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
A stranger comes up to us on the street and says, out of nowhere, “what is the frequency?”
We are likely to assume that he is crazy, or perhaps mistaking us for someone else. Roommate: “There’s a letter for you on the table.” If it’s the same old letter that both of you know well has been there for several days, you may waste some time looking for another one. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: Sentences can be constructed in different ways but have a similar meaning. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
I need a nickel.
It’s me that needs a nickel. What I need is a nickel. A nickel is what I need. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: Do not introduce familiar things as if they were new, as it can be insulting and/or confusing. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
If your roommate says “there’s a letter for you on the table”, and it’s the same old letter that both of you know well has been there for several days, you may waste some time looking for another one. | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Rule: Aspects of language can indicate whether a particular piece of information is “old” or “new”. This reduces the amount of detail needed in talking about it, and still make it obvious for listeners or readers.
“Old information” (usually a noun) occurs early in a sentence and may be referred to using a pronoun. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
When John appeared at the party, he was introduced to Pearl.
She had arrived with her friend Julie. Joan: [Sniffing] “One thing I’ve noticed is clogs are back.” Mary: “Really?” Joan: “Yeah. They’re starting to make a comeback. You see them in the stores more and more, and I said I didn’t think I’d ever see those again. [laughter] Legend:
|
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Reference | Definition: Words we use to identify things that are in some direct relationship to those things and clearly tied to the speaker’s goals/beliefs.
The speaker/writer uses linguistic forms to enable a listener/reader to identify something. Credit to: Yule |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Referring Expression | Definition: Any expression used in an utterance to refer to something or someone. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The choice of expression depends on what the speaker assumes the listener already knows.
There are 4 categories of referring expressions: |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Credit to: شفاء الزهراء |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Referent | Definition: What a word or symbol stands for. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
An actual chair is the referent of the word chair.
Possible referents include government, country, soccer team . . . |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Co-text | Definition: The linguistic material that accompanies the referring expression. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Brazil wins World Cup.
“Wins World Cup” limits the range of possible interpretations. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Context | Definition: The physical environment and speech conventions that have an impact on how the referring expression is interpreted. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The heart attack can’t be moved.
In a hospital, “heart attack” refers to a patient who suffered one. Your ten-thirty just canceled. An office where people are scheduled for appointments or meetings. A couple of rooms have complained about the heat. People who work in a hotel understand that “rooms” are the people occupying the room. The cheese sandwich is in the corner. In a restaurant, the waitpersons refer to the eater by what they’ve ordered. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Attributive Use | Definition: Who/whatever fits the description.
Also possible with definite noun phrases. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The murderer of Smith is insane.
Refers to the possibly unknown person who murdered Smith, whoever that person may be. She wants to marry a man with lots of money. No idea who the guy is, but he’ll have lots of money. Legend:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Referential Use | Definition: One specific entity fits the description. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
The killer escaped.
“The killer” is a specific person, even though no other description or name is used. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Antecedent | Definition: An initial reference, usually the indefinite noun phrase, that is followed by the anaphora. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
John arrived late because traffic held him up.
The pronoun “him” refers to and takes its meaning from “John”, so “John” is the antecedent of “him”. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Postcedent | Definition: The anaphora is followed by what would normally be the antecedent . . . only it comes after. Just to, ya know, really ram that “post” thing home. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
It bothered me that she did not call.
Two violinists were there, at the party. Sam tries to work then, when it is raining. Legend:
Credit to: Antecedent |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Anaphor | Definition: The second or subsequent expression after the antecedent.
The connection of the anaphor with the referent is not always direct. A.k.a. anaphoric reference, anaphoric expression, aphor expression, pro-form Credit to: Shandy |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
I was waiting for the bus, but he drove by without stopping.
The inference is that there is a bus in motion; that “he” is the driver; and, that there is a description of what “I” was doing. Legend:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Anaphora | Definition: A subsequent reference to an already introduced referent(s).
Credit to: Shandy |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Peel and slice six potatoes. Put them in cold salted water.
“Them”, the subsequent reference, is the “six peeled and sliced potatoes”. The bus came on time, but he didn’t stop. The “bus” and “he” do not agree grammatically, but the bus does have a driver, and “he” refers to that bus driver. Legend:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Verbal Anaphora | Definition: A gap, an ellipsis in a phrase or clause, is presented and the listener/reader must identify the missing word(s) by referring back.
A.k.a. verb phrase anaphor, verb phrase ellipsis, zero anaphora |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
Cook for three minutes. Eliminating those potatoes is an ellipsis, expecting the listener to infer that that ellipsis refers to those six sliced potatoes. He did this in under an hour. Legend:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Cataphora | Definition: Reverses the antecedent-anaphora pattern, requiring the use of a postcedent.
It’s less common than anaphora. Credit to: Shandy |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Return to top or post contents |
I turned the corner and almost stepped on it! Can you believe there was a large snake in the middle of the path.
Legend:
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Inference | Definition: Any additional information used by the listener/reader to correctly connect/identify what is said to what must be meant.
Inferring connects prior knowledge to text-based information to create meaning beyond what is directly stated. Credit to: Shandy |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
I enjoy listening to Mozart.
The listener/reader infers that “Mozart” is the composer of the music. Have you seen that blue thing? I don’t like that icky stuff. Mister Nose-in-the-air should arrive any time. Uses an expression that focuses on one feature. Where’s my Shakespeare? The listener infers that the speaker is looking for a book on or written by Shakespeare. |
C’mon, get it out of your system, bitch, whine, moan . . . which words are your pet peeves? Also, please note that I try to be as accurate as I can, but mistakes happen or I miss something. Email me if you find errors, so I can fix them . . . and we’ll all benefit!
Satisfy your curiosity about other Linguistics posts by exploring its homepage or more generally explore the index of self-editing posts. You may also want to explore Book Layout & Formatting Ideas, Formatting Tips, Grammar Explanations, the Properly Punctuated, Word Confusions, Writing Ideas and Resources, and Working Your Website.
Resources for Theoretical Linguistics on Pragmatics
Some of these links may be affiliate links, and I will earn a small percentage, if you should buy it. It does not affect the price you pay.
شفاء الزهراء. “Reference: Pragmatics.” SlideShare.net. 8 Jun 2015. Web. 30 Mar 2021. <https://www.slideshare.net/syifazahro/reference-pragmatics>.
“Antecedent (grammar).” Wikipedia.org. 25 Mar 2021. Web. 30 Mar 2021. <https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Antecedent_(grammar)#Postcedents>.
Austin, John L., Marina Sbisà, and J.O. Urmson, eds. How to Do Things with Words. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 1975.
⸻, J.O. Urmson, and G.J. Warnock, eds. Philosophical Papers. Vol 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961.
⸻ ⸻, and Marina Sbisà, eds. “Lecture VIII.” 2nd ed. Harvard University Press, 1975, p 94-108. <https://sites.uni.edu/boedeker/lecture.pdf>.
Bach, Kent and Robert M. Harnish. Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press, 1979.
Bache, Carl and Niels Davidsen-Nielsen. Mastering English. Walter De Gruyter, 1998.
Boggs, Colleen Glenney. “Speech Acts: Constantive and performative.” TEDEd.com. n.d. Web. 14 March 2021. <https://ed.ted.com/lessons/speech-acts-constative-and-performative-colleen-glenney-boggs>.
Butler, Judith. “Excitable Speech: A Politics of the performative.” MonoSkop.org. n.d. Web. 15 Mar 2021. <https://monoskop.org/images/5/54/Butler_Judith_Excitable_Speech_A_Politics_of_the_Performative_1997.pdf>.
Carston, Robyn and Alison Hall. Hans-Jörg Schmid, ed. “Implicature and Explicature.” Cognitive Pragmatics. Walter de Gruyter, 2012.
Cassin, Barbara. Dictionary of Untranslatables: A Philosophical Lexicon. Princeton, 2014.
Davis, Steven. Searle J.R., Kiefer F., Bierwisch M. eds. “Perlocutions.” Speech Act Theory and Pragmatics. Texts and Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol 10. Springer, Dordrecht: 1980, p 37–55. DOI: <https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8964-1_2>.
Duignan, Brian. “Pragmatics.” Encyclopædia Britannica. n.d. Web. 6 Mar 2021. <https://www.britannica.com/science/pragmatics>.
Horn, Laurence R. The Handbook for Pragmatics. Wiley-Blackwell, 2006.
“Implicature.” Wikipedia.com. 26 Feb 2021. Web. 18 Mar 2021. <https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Implicature>.
Kádár, Dániel Z. “Politeness in Pragmatics.” 29 Mar 2017. Web. 31 Mar 021. <https://oxfordre.com/linguistics/view/10.1093/acrefore/9780199384655.001.0001/acrefore-9780199384655-e-218?mediaType=Article>. Oxford University Press. <https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780199384655.013.218>.
Klammer, Thomas P., Muriel R. Schulz, and Angela Della Volpe. Analyzing English Grammar. 4th ed. Pearson, 2004.
Ladusaw, William. “Meaning (Semantics and Pragmatics).” Linguistic Society.org. n.d. Web. 13 Mar 2021. <https://www.linguisticsociety.org/resource/meaning-semantics-and-pragmatics>.
Mann, William C. and Maite Taboada. “Intro to RST Rhetorical Structure Theory.” Simon Fraser University. n.d. Web. 29 Mar 2021. <https://www.sfu.ca/rst/01intro/intro.html>.
⸻; and Sandra A. Thompson. “Rhetorical Structure Theory: Toward a functional theory of text organization.” University of Pennsylvania. n.d. Web. 28 Mar 2021. <https://www.cis.upenn.edu/~nenkova/Courses/cis700-2/rst.pdf>.
⸻, Christian M.I.M. Matthiessen, and Sandra A. Thompson. “Rhetorical Structure Theory and Text Analysis.” ResearchGate. Nov 1989. Web. 28 Mar 2021. <https://www.researchgate.net/publication/235178249_Rhetorical_Structure_Theory_and_Text_Analysis>. Uploaded by Christian M.I.M. Matthiessen.
Nordquist, Richard. “Conversational Implicature Definition and Examples: It’s not what you say, but what you mean.” ThoughtCo.com. 4 Feb 2020. Web. 21 Mar 2021. <https://www.thoughtco.com/conversational-implicature-speech-acts-1689922>.
⸻, “English Language Sentence Structure: How meaning is derived from the syntax of a sentence.” 4 Nov 2019. Web. 30 Mar 2021. <https://www.thoughtco.com/sentence-structure-english-grammar-1691891>.
⸻, “Explicature (Speech Acts).” Glossary of Grammatical and Rhetorical Terms. ThoughtCo. 19 Feb 2020. Web. 21 Mar 2021. <https://www.thoughtco.com/explicature-speech-acts-1690622>.
⸻, “Locutionary Act Definition in Speech-Act Theory: The act of making a meaningful utterance.” 18 July 2019. Web. 15 Mar 2021. <https://www.thoughtco.com/locutionary-act-speech-1691257>.
⸻, “Politeness Strategies in English Grammar.” Glossary of Grammatical and Rhetorical Terms. ThoughtCo.com. 14 Jan 2020. Web. 31 Mar 2021. <https://www.thoughtco.com/politeness-strategies-conversation-1691516>.
⸻, “Pragmatics Gives Context to Language: Body language and tone of voice augment actual words.” ThoughtCo.com. 11 Aug 2019. Web. 13 Mar 2021. <https://www.thoughtco.com/pragmatics-language-1691654>. He makes an interesting point on how helpful this is in teaching pragmatics to autistic children.
Partee, Barbara H. “Formal Semantics, Lecture 8: Conventional Implicatures.” University of Massachusetts. 24 Apr 2009. Web. 21 Mar 2021. <https://people.umass.edu/partee/MGU_2009/materials/MGU098_2up.pdf>.
“Performative.” Glottopedia.org. 2 Mar 2018. Web. 19 Mar 2021. <http://www.glottopedia.org/index.php/Performative>.
“Politeness Theory.” Wikipedia.org. 9 Mar 2021. Web. 31 Mar 2021. <https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Politeness_theory#Politeness_strategies>.
Potts, Christopher. “Conventional Implicatures, a Distinguished Class of Meanings.” Stanford. 25 Nov 2005. Web. 21 Mar 2021. <https://web.stanford.edu/~cgpotts/papers/potts-interfaces.pdf>.
“Pragmatics.” Lecture 13. Linguistics 001. University of Pennsylvania. Fall 2007. Web. 6 Mar 2021. <https://www.ling.upenn.edu/courses/Fall_2007/ling001/pragmatics.html>.
Richards, Jack. “Teaching Speaking #1 — Conversational Routines.” Pedagogy. World of Better Learning. Cambridge University Press. 1 Feb 2016. Web. 21 Mar 2021. <https://www.cambridge.org/elt/blog/2016/02/01/teaching-speaking-1/>.
Schiffman, H. “Language Use: Functional Approaches to Syntax.” Handout for EDUC 537. Speech Acts and Conversation. Educational Linguistics. University of Pennsylvania. 27 Nov 1997. Web. 19 Mar 2021. <https://www.sas.upenn.edu/~haroldfs/edling/handouts/speechacts/spchax2.html>.
Searle, John. Speech Acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969.
“Semantics vs. Pragmatics.” Study Smarter. n.d. Web. 15 Mar 2023. <https://www.studysmarter.us/explanations/english/pragmatics/semantics-vs-pragmatics/>.
Shandy, Febri. “Pragmatic Reference and Inference.” SlideShare.net. 24 Nov 2013. Web. 30 Mar 2021. <https://www.slideshare.net/FebriShandy/presentation1-28571111>.
“Speech Acts and Events.” Focus and Content. Pragmatics. Ello.us. n.d. Web. 17 Mar 2021. <http://www.ello.uos.de/field.php/Pragmatics/PragmaticsSpeechActsandEvents>.
“Speech Acts Classifications.” Cultural Studies Now. 4 Jan 2018. Web. 15 Mar 2021. <http://culturalstudiesnow.blogspot.com/2018/01/speech-acts-classifications.html>.
“Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.” Stanford University. n.d. Web. 20 Feb 2021. <https://plato.stanford.edu>.
Thomas, Jenny. Meaning in Interaction: An Introduction to Pragmatics. 1st ed. Oxfordshire: Routledge, 2015.
Thompson, Jennifer. “Performatives and Constatives Compared: A Summary.” English 456: C20 Criticism and Theory. University of California-Irvine. n.d. Web. 14 Mar 2021. <https://www.ajdrake.com/e456_spr_03/materials/guides/gd_performatives.htm>.
Vanderkeven, Daniel and Susumu Kubo. “Introduction.” Essays in Speech Act Theory. John Benjamins Publishing Company: 2001, pp 1–21.
Wardhaugh, Ronald. How Conversation Works. Wiley Computer Publishing, 1985, p 74.
“What is Linguistics?” UC Santa Cruz. 4 Aug 2017. Web. 6 Dec 2020. <https://linguistics.ucsc.edu/about/what-is-linguistics.html>.
“What is Linguistics and Why Study It?” College of Social & Behavioral Sciences. University of Arizona. n.d. Web. 6 Dec 2020. <https://linguistics.arizona.edu/content/what-linguistics-and-why-study-it-0>.
“What is Pragmatics?” All About Linguistics. n.d. Web. 6 Mar 2021. <https://all-about-linguistics.group.shef.ac.uk/branches-of-linguistics/pragmatics/what-is-pragmatics/>.
“Written Assignment — Illocutionary Classification.” Linguistics 105- Law and Language. University of California-San Diego. n.d. Web. 21 Mar 2021. <http://grammar.ucsd.edu/courses/lign105/illoc-ans.html>.
Yule, George. The Study of Language. 4th ed. Cambridge University Press, 2010.
Pinterest Photo Credits:
A Conversation is Khalid Albaih‘s own work and is under the CC BY 2.0 license, via Flickr.